By Lord Timothy Dexter
INTRODUCTION
I
am not a dog lover. My initial reaction to Professor Engel’s The Myth of the Litigious Society was me
saying that a dog that doesn’t bark sounds like a well-trained dog.
Professor
Engel’s Myth looks critically at 4
items: (1) the popular misconception of American litigiousness; (2) what the
reality is and reasons for it; (3) the consequences of the misconception’s
popularity; and (4) some direction as to what the next steps could be. According
to the misconception, Americans sue each other at the drop of a hat for mostly
illegitimate reasons. Our legal system is stuck in a court-clogged and lawsuit-obsessed
Hell. Ridiculous personal injury, medical malpractice, and other typical first-year-of-law-school torts claims overwhelm our courts, which should be reserved
for legitimate claims (pg. 66, para. 3). The amount of these lawsuits is either
already outrageous or increasing. The problem is not one of pursuing equal
justice under the law, but one of unscrupulous ambulance chasers conning
innocent or naïve defendants into paying out damages to litigation-crazed
plaintiffs suffering from bogus or exaggerated injuries.
The
reality couldn’t be more different, Americans do not sue each other for much of
anything at all. In 2012, government data showed that accidents resulted in 38
million Americans being seriously injured, and 127,200 more were killed (pg. 4,
para. 3). Despite the likelihood that many of these injuries were likely the
result of someone else’s actions or negligence, Americans choose to “lump” (they
do not take any action, legal or
other) in response to 91% of injuries. Only 4% of the injured even hire an
attorney, only 2% file a lawsuit (table 2.1, pg. 23). Despite evidence disproving
the litigiousness myth, real-world consequences from believing the myth have occurred.
Millions of Americans are going through their lives dealing with some injury and
its results on their own without the aid of the law. Professor Engel asks us, how
can the reality be so different from the popular perception? For a variety of
political, economic, and social reasons, Myth
tells us why we as Americans do not sue each other. The political reasons include
examples of elected officials passing tort reform measures to reduce and restrict
claims to stop in out-of-control plaintiffs (pg. 12, paras. 1-2). The economic reasons
include expensive legal fees from attorneys who couldn’t pursue a claim unless
the defendant could realistically pay something (pg. 101, para. 3). The social
reasons include how those that pursue claims are labelled troublemakers, liars,
or whiners (pg. 159, para. 2).
Professor
Engel does not call for more lawsuits. He does not believe this would be the
best solution to the problem. He asks us to make a cultural shift to make our
torts and wider justice system fairer. If the goal of tort law is to make the
injured party whole, there is no doubt that the American system comes up short.
My
most significant response after reading Myth
is that Professor Engel should next point his research in the direction of the
world of advocacy for survivors of sexual violence, harassment, and
discrimination. Myth’s so-called
missing plaintiff, an injury victim who opts for lumping instead of claiming, reminds
me of the conditions that have led to #MeToo. I do not mean to say it’s an apples
to apples comparison. I recognize that trying to convince an American law
professor to conduct further research on what can be done about the case of the
missing plaintiff by focusing on a movement that has yielded concerns about due
process and free speech may seem like a misguided idea. While I personally
support #MeToo, I am not suggesting it would on its own be able to solve the
case of the missing plaintiff. I am merely saying that I see a link between the
problems that led to #MeToo’s proliferation and Myth’s problem of the missing plaintiff. The #MeToo movement is the
result of decades of organizing, advocacy, and research that involved a group
that was blamed for their pain, called liars, and cast out of professional and
personal circles for daring to go after their own abuser. Underneath #MeToo is
an army of victim’s advocates, social workers, academics, and more importantly individuals
with personal stories of abuse and harassment that have recently captured the
attention of the country and slowly begun to shift the narrative on the evils
of sex-based discrimination. If we are to find our missing plaintiff, if we are
to figure out why the dog isn’t barking, if we are to help tort law achieve its
goal of making injured people whole, then injury sufferers themselves will need
their own version of #MeToo.
Professor
Engel is an excellent early explorer, charting the waters for future research
on this matter (pg. 171, para. 1). With Myth,
he has arrived back at the home harbor after years at sea, sailing on ships
named for his fantastic and brilliant research assistants. Our professor gave his
1L torts students an assignment to write a reflection essay answering three
questions about Professor Engel’s Myth.
He also encouraged us to be creative in writing those answers. Consider me one
of the amateur explorers who meets Professor Engel in the harbor. From my amateur
cartography I have drawn a map suggesting where this expedition for the “missing
plaintiff” could go next. Obviously, law school is not traditional graduate
school. I don’t have research assistants. I’m not writing a doctoral thesis. This
essay is the result of a series of thoughts I had while reading this book. As that
amateur explorer, I am trying to tell Professor Engel, “El Dorado could be here
on the map, but I can’t make any promises and I don’t have the time to figure
it out myself.”
REFLECTION
Myth did teach me a lot about the
reality of litigiousness in America, but more important than what it taught me
the book reframed the problem in my mind and how I think it relates to a wider
social and cultural malady impacting our country: victim blaming. To put it
simply, I just hadn’t thought of it that way before. How I viewed the
stereotypes of injury victims changed and Professor Engel helped me realize that these victims are subject to all the other
drawbacks that trauma survivors suffer from. To be clear, Myth is not just about victim blaming. It’s mentioned as only one
of many reasons why potential plaintiffs lump their injuries. But to me, Professor
Engel’s overall characterization of how injury victims are viewed by
themselves, our society at large, their communities, and even their support
networks sounds a lot like the experiences of victim blaming that are common to
other survivors of injury and violence.
Myth only describes victim blaming in the
context of the case of the missing plaintiff.
Professor Engel gives us research which suggests injury sufferers do not pursue
legal claims because they blame themselves or are otherwise convinced that
their own actions or moral misgivings caused their injury (pg. 48, para. 2). Worse
still, when the personal circumstances of the injury sufferer cloud the exact
cause of the pain experienced, it is common for him or her to resort to
self-blame or for others to blame them (pg. 90, para. 4). This blame increases
the likelihood that an injury sufferer will choose to lump instead of claim,
stifling any chance to be made whole.
Before
reading Myth, I intellectually
understood the concepts behind why many injured people cannot get a fair chance
under the law. Implicit and explicit biases, small and large, plague policy
makers, jurors, and judges just as often as they do members of the public. Personally,
I only thought that the reason Americans don’t sue was strictly due to the
economics of it. I thought that the justice system kept out millions of needy
litigants because of their inability to pay lawyers. To be clear, this is still
a major part of the problem. However, Myth
showed me that this is only one piece of the puzzle. People do not just lump their
injuries because they can’t afford a lawyer, or because the damages would be
too small to justify hiring one. I knew that injury victims often cannot behave
rationally nor make a series of decisions along a reasonably linear timeline in
response to their injury. I didn’t fully understand or appreciate how or why it
applied to tort law and our civil dispute system. Professor Engel gives us a
better model to assess how individuals deal with injury (pg. 70, Fig. 5.3). The
better model, “deliberately avoids building in any particular normative
preferences—nor assumes that people should
think rationally, they should
maximize benefits and mitigate costs, they should
keep litigation in mind as a last resort if all else fails, they should conduct negotiations in the
shadow of the law. Instead, it leaves open the possibility that all these
things may or may not actually occur. And it remains neutral as to whether the
world would be better if they did” (pg. 81, para 2). When I get to use my
magic wand, I will further explain why this model reminded me of the activism
around sexual discrimination in our country, and why I feel strongly that the
next step is to research this and movements like #MeToo.
Last
among things I learned and how my conception of our justice system changed, before
Myth I truly did not understand how
powerfully our communities can convince us to lump and not claim. Professor
Engel makes a literary reference to Sherlock Holmes when he asks why the dog
doesn’t bark, why people don’t sue (pgs. 3-4). With literature in mind, chapter
nine reminded me of all the dystopian future novels I love. A common theme in
most of them is that the protagonists explore individuality before eventually
succumbing to what their societies force them to believe. In these novels, as
in real life, whatever one’s social web suggests is the proper response to something
(be it injury or anything really) becomes the normal, rational, and reasonable
way to do so. Specifically, chapter nine reminded me of Yevgeny Zamyatin’s dystopian
sci-fi book We. In We, after the protagonist is effectively
“re-educated” by the totalitarian state, he declares that his society’s rules
are the end-point of human development, that all opinions critical of the
rulers are unreasonable. While he began to question everything, his reformed
self declares that “reason must prevail” over the disorder of individualism.
In
chapter nine, Professor Engel writes that the American belief that we behave as
autonomous selves is a myth unto itself (pg. 147, para. 3). He tells us the
story of Miranda Compton. After Ms. Compton’s daughter is severely injured in
an accident her ex-husband convinces her to hire an attorney and pursue
damages, of which she eventually receives very little and her marriage ends,
and she becomes reliant upon welfare and other benefits (pgs. 149-51). Ms.
Compton goes on to feel very guilty for this. Her minister even suggests that
her guilt might be justified because she sought money for her daughter’s injury
instead of reaching out to God. While the entire ordeal of the injury and the
lawsuit were ongoing, her support network constantly reminded her that was a
natural (i.e. “correct”) way to deal with her daughter’s injury (pgs. 158-59).
A big takeaway from chapter nine is that our own support network can convince
us that lumping is morally preferable to claiming (pg. 162, para 2). Ms.
Compton went from being a woman who not only chose to claim, but a court found that
her daughter’s injuries were actionable, even if the monetary damages were small.
Despite winning her case, effectively being told by our legal system that she was
“right,” her friends, family and minister told her she was being unreasonable.
She becomes the protagonist in We, going
from pursuing justice for her daughter to believing that reason must prevail
over the disorder of litigation.
I
do not mean to suggest that I believe we are living in a dystopian future, but
I do find it necessary, and chilling, to point out that the language used in
chapter nine did jar my memory about this genre of literature. Professor Engel
himself says that most injurer tort defendants have deep pockets whereas injured
tort plaintiffs are usually of modest means and lower social status (pg. 101,
para 3). I don’t think it’s too far-fetched to say that the 91% of people that
lump, who are overwhelmingly of modest means or are low income, whose broken
bodies impair their abilities to operate within this world and take part as
full participants in our society, they are living in that dystopia whether they
see it that way or not. Before Myth,
I had not considered the lumpers as part of the Epsilon class.
In
short, my conception of the American civil dispute system after Myth is how, through victim blaming and normalization
of injury and inaction, society maintains and reinforces many of the wider
problems of inequality in our country as whole. In our court rooms, an
impartial judge with an impartial jury unconsciously keeps the haves and
have-nots apart in justice.
MY MAGIC WAND
I
would make three changes with my magic wand.
The
first would be to psychologically empower all injury sufferers in order to
grant them a say in the decisions that affect their lives. I would get them to
a place where maybe they still don’t choose to sue, but that they could
conceivably be made whole. The U.S. tort system would be readily available to
them, with hotlines, interpreters, social workers and even affordable lawyers on
call and ready to make sure an empowered injured class could access the legal
system if they chose to. Obviously, this solution would require billions in
taxpayer dollars being spent on have-nots. If current political rhetoric is
anything to go by, there would likely be political fallout for adopting such a
progressive and utopian judicial system.
The
second wave would free up elected officials to act in the interests of
everybody and not just donors, primary election voters (usually 15-30% of all
registered voters who are usually more partisan) and legislative leaders (speakers,
majority leaders, committee chairmen, etc.). If all rank and file legislators
could act reasonably on these issues, the victim blaming and unfair tort reform
measures would never see a vote. With all due respect to Professor Engel, he is
wrong to believe that policy makers such as elected officials adopt tort reform
because they believe the litigiousness myth. I can say that many of them most
likely do not. Many elected officials are lawyers themselves, some even choose
to practice law while serving their legislative terms (especially in states
where legislators are not paid or don’t serve for a full-time legislature). They
are lobbied frequently by community legal aid activists who take on low-income
clients. They are aware of the realities inside the judicial branches that they
approve the budget appropriations for. Whether it’s abortion, labor unions,
public education, or tort reform, legislators are more likely to be aware of reality
than academics and media credit them for. They take politically expedient
actions based on the voting preferences of their constituents, the giving
preferences of their donors, or the political pressures of leadership within
their bicameral bodies. Realistically in the U.S., if legislators were to adopt
“anti-tort reform” as a platform issue they would likely pay for it at the
ballot box because their constituents probably do believe the litigiousness
myth, or their wealthy donors probably include torts defendants who’d stop
donating, or they could face a demotion in seniority from leadership for
upsetting the status quo.
The
third wave of my wand would be for lumpers to have their own #MeToo movement.
This is sort of an amalgamation of the previous two waves. Empowering victims
and moving policy are two essential elements of #MeToo. But if Professor Engel
is calling for a paradigm shift where injury sufferers can take charge of their
condition, then he should direct his ships named for his research assistants
towards the lands named #MeToo.
Like
in Myth where it is said that many
people do not sue because of community pressures such as limited future
employment opportunities, being ostracized from social webs, the thousands of
organizers behind #MeToo have dealt with survivors and harassment victims who
lump their traumas and take no action for the same reasons. Like the lumpers, #MeToo
has organized people who originally rationalized and normalized their
experiences and chose to take no action. Most importantly, a victim of
sex-based discrimination suffers trauma that inhibits the ability to think or
behave rationally, and there is a professional support network trained to deal
with these victims directly now. The better model Professor Engel asks us to
adopt to view how real people respond to injury has already been adopted in
similar form by activists organizing survivors of sexual trauma and
discrimination.
Considering
the feasibility, a #MeToo for injury victims would deal with the same social,
political and economic reactions that sex-based discrimination sufferers have
for generations. There’s no getting around that. However, these activists are
experts in this field. They have dealt with victims who were labelled as
troublemakers, were told that they were “asking for it,” or even told that
their abuse was “natural.” That is exactly what Myth says is happening to injury sufferers. Professor Engel should
reach out to the leaders in #MeToo. The dog might not be barking in the world
of sex-based discrimination, but she’s certainly beginning to growl. A start’s
a start. #MeToo’s aim is to take people who otherwise would’ve gone without
justice and now have a shot at getting something.
#MeToo
and Professor Engel are both concerned about making injury victims whole, which
seems like a reasonable objective. This amateur explorer believes that reason
must prevail.
No comments:
Post a Comment