To have such pervasive and compelling rhetoric of out-of-control tort litigation at the same time as research shows that fewer
and fewer people are actually making claims suggests that something deeper may
be at stake than simply making injured bodies whole. David Engel says as much
in the introduction to his book, The Myth of the Litigious Society: Why We Don’t
Sue. As he traces the evolution of tort law from strict liability, to a
negligence standard, to the mid-20th century almost-distributive approach, to
today’s damage’s caps and re-affirmation of no-fault liability, he is also
tracing the socio-cultural view of personal responsibility in the United States. David M. Engel, The
Myth of the Litigious Society: Why We Don’t Sue 9-10
(2016).
The ways in which injury comes to
be seen as actionable interests me the most, and I credit Engel for bringing it
to the fore. Sarah S. Lochlann Jain (cited in Engel) notes that “[i]njury is a
project of translation through which the co-constitutive effects of agency are
interpreted and distinguished.” The
Politics of Product Design and Safety Law in the United States 17
(2006). Jain’s point can be read to encompass how it is that some injuries, and
that mechanism which caused the injury (products, or conduct, or social
conditions), come to be understood as actionable. In the 1950s and 1960s,
cars without seatbelts were the norm; today the vehicle would be considered defective
without them. A chainsaw sold without a chain brake? Prescription drugs without
a child-proof lid?
Of course, notable about those
three examples is that they would all fall under the rubric products liability,
and therefore the no-fault state of culpability that is strict liability. I
suspect that much of the reason for the dearth of personal injury litigation
can be explained by insurance schemes that so often apply when fault is
attributed to the accident. Car accidents provide an illustration – most
coverage includes compensation for bodily injury. Although, as Engel argues, an
insurance settlement may be less than a victim would receive had they lodged a
formal claim, a potential claimant is less likely to pursue a claim once they
have a check in their hands. Engel,
supra at 165. Workplace accidents,
another example where injury-causing mishaps are common, are covered by the
state-sponsored insurance program of workers' compensation.
While I think that Engel’s premise presents a much-needed
contribution to the debate between excessive litigation and tort reform, the
book overall left me unfulfilled. I attribute this response more to my
dissatisfaction with tort law itself than with Engel’s thesis. While I
understand that tort concerns itself with disputes (that result in harm)
between two individuals (or corporate bodies), most of what harms bodies comes
not from the snow left un-shoveled by the neighbor, but rather by the harmful
environments, chemicals, foods, and occupations that are disproportionately
used, encountered, eaten, and undertaken by people with disproportionately fewer
recourses. Not every potential tort claim is treated equally, or even
recognized, in civil litigation. Not every person is positioned equally in
relation to access to the civil legal system. And not every person faces the
same likelihood of injury. Those who inflict injury are likely to be wealthy,
those who sustain injury are likely to be poor. Id. at 139. If the goal of tort law is to redress wrongs and compensate
victims that are unfairly harmed, then it is worth asking what its role can be
when wrongs are systemic rather than accidental.
To that end, envisioning a tort
system that is able to redress wrongs with equity but without disturbing the sacred
corrective and distributive dichotomy is a challenge. My initial reaction is to
push for an expanded conception of duty, or a flexible interpretation of
causation. Let wide the gates! Tear down the wall! However, even my
bleeding-heart balks a little at this proposition. The tort system is not and
should not be, fundamentally, a system that seeks to punish. Further, to put
people back in the place they were before the injury may be a desirable aim,
but not one that is necessarily has a lasting effect. Had the Pelman plaintiffs been awarded damages
for the harmful effects of chicken nuggets and French fries, McDonald's may have been forced by public pressure to
change the nutritional content of their product. But cigarettes can still be
purchased at the corner store.
More significant would be a
socio-economic shift that brought affordable and healthy options to
neighborhoods where fast food is the only option. And that is not the purview of
tort. I would like to see a New Zealand-style system of compensation played out
alongside a robust welfare state while retaining tort law that allows for
egregious wrongs to be remedied through civil litigation. As seen in the Stella Liebeck case, tort law
can be enormously effective in changing injurious practices. Such monumental
changes, however, are rare, and as Engel shows, the majority of injury victims
go uncompensated. Compensating those victims, so they can return to being
productive members of society, is the responsibility of the State, but should
not perhaps take place in the courtroom.
No comments:
Post a Comment